What is Art? : An Essay in the Age of AI Technology (by Tomoki Akimaru)

 

What is Art? Art is the complementary concept to the technology.

In ancient Greece, the word “technē” was used to refer to any “skill” by which a person achieved some goal. In other words, “technē” meant all kinds of “skills” such as painting, sculpture, architecture, surveying, healing, fighting, horse riding, cooking, oratory, lovemaking, astrology, and so on.

When ancient Greece was ruled by ancient Rome and “technē” was translated into Latin as “ars,” its meaning did not change. In general, “ars” also meant any “skill” to achieve some goal.

After the collapse of ancient Rome, Europe entered the Christian Middle Ages, but even in the Middle Ages, the meaning of the Latin concept of “ars” did not change.

In Europe, however, the meaning of the concept of “ars” changed from the Renaissance in the 14th century to the Scientific Revolution in the 17th century.

◇ ◇ ◇

The rationalism that emerged during the Renaissance eventually brought about the Scientific Revolution, and a new science was established that was different from conventional science.

As represented by Aristotle’s (BC384-BC322) Organon, even in ancient Greece, “science” as a logical explanation of things existed, but it was subjective. However, for the first time in human history, an objective science that is not subjective – “modern science” – was established in modern Europe.

The objectivity of modern science is based on quantification. In other words, just as “1 + 1 = 2” remains the same no matter when, where, or who solves it, modern science, which deals with the world in a quantitative way, is universally valid.

Jacob Burckhardt (1818-1897), in his Culture of the Italian Renaissance (1860), characterized the Renaissance as “the discovery of the world and of man” [1]. As René Descartes (1596-1650) explained in his Discourse on Method (1637), the core of Renaissance rationalism is the belief that the world is recognized in terms of quantity not but quality, and that human reason can decipher the laws of this quantitative world.

Leonardo da Vinci (1452-1519) realized this Renaissance rationalism through one-point perspective and anatomical drawings, and Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) put it into practice in his experiments with falling objects from the Leaning Tower of Pisa. Francis Bacon (1561-1626), in his Novum Organum (New Organon) (1620), a response to Aristotle’s Organon, praised modern science, which develops through the spiral movement of such observations and experiments, as “knowledge is power”. Bacon expected that modern science would actually improve the world through its practical application, and predicted the ideal future in New Atlantis (1627).

What is interesting here is that since the Renaissance, in the practical application of this developing “modern science,” gradually from what had traditionally been called “ars (technē),” only those parts that were linked to “modern science” came to be called “technique.” The characteristic of technique, like modern science, is that it is quantifiable and objective, and therefore reproducible. Eventually, modern science and technique were combined into a single word, “technology.”

On the other hand, what remains after the “technique” has been extracted from all the “ars (technē)” is called “art.” In short, the definition of “art” is the skill that is not the technique. Because it can only be defined negatively, not positively, no one has ever been able to fully define “art” until now.

The characteristic of art, in contrast to technology, is that it is subjective and therefore not quantifiable or reproducible. In other words, art is a matter of quality, not quantity. Thus, while technology can teach or be taught, art cannot teach or be taught. Moreover, no one can create the exact same work of art again. Even if Leonardo were to paint the Mona Lisa (c. 1503-17) (Fig. 1) again, it would not be exactly the same, because art is based on the human heart which is alive and irreversible.

 

Fig. 1 Leonardo da Vinci Mona Lisa c. 1503-17

 

Such subjectivity makes art relevant to issues of personality. As an anecdote quoted by Heinrich Wölfflin’s (1864-1945) Principals of Art History (1915) [2] shows, if several painters were to paint the same landscape, the resulting paintings would never be the same, for each person has their own personality.

Art is subjective because it is based on the human mind. The awareness that it is none other than I who painted it appears as a signature, and the self-consciousness motivates the artist to paint a self-portrait. Both the signature and the self-portrait were new modes of painting based on individuality that emerged during the Renaissance.

And as the greatest aspect of individuality, art involves the concept of genius. When one sees an extraordinary high-quality work of art based on individuality, such as Leonardo’s Mona Lisa, one cannot help but recognize the existence of genius. Although highly trained persons or machines with advanced technology may perfectly copy the Mona Lisa, they cannot create the Mona Lisa from nothing. Therefore, the essence of art as the most unique and unrepeatable is an original idea.

◇ ◇ ◇

As in the case of Leonardo, technology and art were not yet clearly separated during the Renaissance, but as time went on the two gradually diverged.

In the process, a movement also arose to distinguish between “artisan” and “artist,” elevating the artist above the artisan. That is, a distinction was made between low and high class artisans, with high class artisans being regarded as artists.

In ancient Greece, the free mental activity of citizens was considered superior to the simple physical labor of slaves. Based on this tradition, in modern Europe, a trend emerged to include “art” in the “liberal arts,” which had been inherited as a symbol of the free mental activity of citizens.

First, formative objects can be divided into four categories: painting, sculpture, architecture, and crafts. Of these, works that are not simple physical labor but in which free mental activity can be felt are considered “art,” and their creators are called not low-class artisans but high-class artisans, that is, “artists.”

Here, the concept of “disegno” was praised as an indicator of this free mental activity. Disegno is the common root of “dessin” and “design.” More precisely, dessin is to perceive the world with rational lines rather than emotional colors, and design is to construct an artificial world through reason. In the case of formative objects, whether they are painting, sculpture, architecture, or crafts only those in which the effect of this disegno can be felt are considered to be works of art.

In addition, a hierarchy was formed within such artistic genres: the more free the human mind is, the more valuable it is, and sight is considered to have a higher degree of free activity of the spirit than touch. Thus, the higher the visual element, the higher the value, and the ranking is painting, sculpture, architecture, and crafts.

This hierarchy implies the superiority of human reason over nature. Everyday life is less valuable because it is grounded in nature. This leads to the art for appreciation being ranked higher than the art for practical use. In contrast to “practical art,” the less practical an art is, the more it becomes “fine art.” Here, “fine” means “non-practical,” and in order of the degree of purely visual appreciation, the ranking is again painting, sculpture, architecture, and crafts. In the appreciation arts, painting is first and sculpture is second. Architecture is included in both the appreciation art and the practical art. Crafts as practical art are excluded from the appreciative art.

Eventually, “fine” was omitted, and the one word “Art” came to mean “appreciation art.” By the way, in Japan, “fine” was translated as “beautiful” and “appreciation art” was translated as “beautiful art.” This was probably influenced by the French “beaux-arts” and the German “schöne Künste.”

Furthermore, the term “practical” also includes religious aspects. Therefore, if the pursuit of pure appreciation in “art” is called “modernism,” then crafts and religious arts would be excluded from modernism.

◇ ◇ ◇

However, even though the interest in the art gradually increased after the Renaissance, the division between the art and the technique was not so clear because they were within the same manual skill. This is partly because the technique was first necessary to accurately express the human mind as the art. In other words, the technical element is always inseparably included in the art.

As Raymond Williams’ Culture and Society (1958) [3] shows, the difference between the art and the technique became clearly conscious when the development of the technology brought about the Industrial Revolution since the 18th century.

As industrial products made by machines appeared, the difference between them and works of art, which are the creation of the minds and hands of living human beings, became clearly felt. This led a widespread interest in the art from the 18th century, although the concept of art was not clearly defined.

In addition, since the 18th century, the Industrial Revolution led people to require economic and political freedoms, bringing about the Civil Revolution and spreading awareness of human rights. In this context, the art became increasingly highly valued as self-expression through individuality. However, in focusing solely on the art, the background that the art was originally formed as the complementary concept to the technology is overlooked, resulting in a situation in which only interpretations of the concept of the art became diverse. For example, definitions such as “art is the free activity of the mind” or “art is a self-expression through individuality” are partial and incomplete.

To make things more complicated, from ancient Greece until the 19th century, it was believed that “mimesis” was the measure of the value of art (once the concept of “art” was established, it was applied to objects before the concept was established). In other words, it was long believed that the value of art was determined by the degree of objective representation. The high value placed on realistic paintings can be seen in the contest between Zeuxis and Pallasius in ancient Greece, as recorded in Pliny the Elder’s Natural History. [4]

However, in the 19th century, when the reproductive technologies such as photography were invented and developed, objective representation came to be recognized as a matter of the technique and not of the art. As a result, as Walter Benjamin (1892-1940) said in his Work of Art in the Age of Reproduction Technology (1936-37) [5], in painting, the emphasis began to shift to subjective expression based on the artist’s personality.

Émile Zola (1840-1902), a supporter of Impressionism, insisted in an 1866 Salon review that “art is a corner of nature seen through temperament.” [6] As Richard Shiff (1955-) argued in his Cézanne and the End of Impressionism (1984) [7], the Impressionists still aimed at an objective representation of the senses, but this in turn became a suggestion for the subjective expression that came after Impressionism, leading to various expressionistic tendencies.

Abstract painting, which flourished in the early 20th century, is generally recognized as purely subjective expression without reference to any external object, and this mainstreaming of abstract painting has continued unabated to the present day.

Another major tendency in 20th century art was the pursuit of a more pure art that was less trained and less technicalized. Pablo Picasso (1881-1973) idealized to create the painting like an innocent child. Jean Dubuffet (1901-1985) focused on “art brut (raw art)” without formal art education [8]. With these as background, interest in “outsider art” has been growing worldwide since the late 20th century.

◇ ◇ ◇

As we approach the quarter century mark of the 21st century, the most talked-about topic is how the development of AI technology is shaking the conventional concept of “art”. Are formative objects made by AI technology really art? However, in order to discuss this issue, we must first conceptually clarify what “art” is.

In this paper, I defined “art” as the skill that is not the technique. In other words, the characteristic of art is that it is subjective, unquantifiable, and therefore irreproducible. Additionally, the essence of art is the free mental activity of a living artist, and the core is an original idea. Therefore, I believe that forms randomly produced by AI technology are not “art,” no matter how intricate they may be. This is because they lack the internal inevitability that comes from a lively human mind. No matter how high-speed the calculations, the randomness of AI technology is not the free spirit of a living person, but merely an approximation of it.

The shapes produced by AI technology are not the art, just as the accidental stains formed by nature are not the art. Essentially, anything that is not created by the human soul is not the art (however, if nature or machines are anthropomorphized, it is possible to metaphorically call the shapes produced by them “art”).

Conversely, if a person finally adds something to such a non-human’s work, that person’s minds are expressed in it, and it becomes his/her work of art. Just as a work used by photograph can be a work of art depending on the photographer’s personality, a work used by AI technology can be a work of art depending on the programmer’s personality. However, the problem that we never get tired of looking at landscapes or paintings, but eventually we do get tired of looking at photographs and composite photographs, may also apply to composite forms produced by AI technology.

 

Fig. 2 The Next Rembrandt by Microsoft, Delft University of Technology, etc., 2016.

 

The more difficult problem is when AI technology is used to skillfully manipulate forms created by the human mind. Since the forms created by someone in the past reflect his/her minds, representing them can make people feel as if his/her minds are still there.

Moreover, if analyzing the data of the common patterns in forms created by an artist and newly composing their features, a creation from nothing based on an original idea, that is, the artist’s “new work” not but mere copy, which was previously impossible, is now theoretically possible. In fact, already in 2016, The Next Rembrandt (Fig. 2), in which all of Rembrandt’s 346 works have been analyzed, their features newly composed, and output by a 3D printer, as if Rembrandt himself had painted it.

However, no matter how much Rembrandt’s minds are reflected in the forms recomposed by AI technology, it is not spring from Rembrandt’s living spirit. Therefore, in this case, such paintings produced by AI technology are still a kind of imitation, and even if it is considered a work of art, it is still nothing but a fake. This is probably the reason why, even though we may sometimes feel grateful that AI technology can recompose what the deceased people left behind, we also feel an instinctive aversion to it, as if it is somehow violating to the dignity of these people.

A genuine work of art is born from the spirit of a living person. In this sense, the products of AI technology are not genuine works of art. Then, what can AI technology bring to art? It is a new way to appreciate art.

By comparing multiple photographic plates, Wölfflin realized the “pure visibility” discussed by Konrad Fiedler (1841-1895) in his Origin of Artistic Activity (1887) [9] and constructed an art history as a history of style. André Malraux (1901-1976), in his Imaginary Museum (1947), also envisioned a history of world art in which photography would extract every formative object as dessin image [10]. The development of technology gives rise to new ways of appreciating art.

The definition of art as the skill that is not the technique and its characteristics as subjective, unquantifiable and irreproducible based on the spirit of a living person has never been, is and always will be the same.

However, it can be said that AI technology has created a new way of appreciating art that did not previously exist. Just as comparing multiple photographs of an artist’s artworks can reveal the artist’s personal style, using AI technology to deep learn the artworks of an artist can reveal the artist’s personal style and even create provisional samples.

In conclusion, although formative works produced by AI technology are not genuine works of art, it can be appreciated as a work of art insofar as it reflects the human mind.

 

[1] Jacob Burckhardt, Die Cultur der Renaissance in Italien: ein Versuch, Schweighauser, 1860.

[2] Heinrich Wölfflin, Kunstgeschichtliche Grundbegriffe, das Problem der Stilentwicklung in der neueren Kunst, Bruckmann, 1915.

[3] Raymond Williams, Culture and Society: 1780-1950, Chatto & Windus, 1958.

[4] Pliny the Elder, Natural History: A Selection, translated by John F. Healey, Penguin Classics, 1991.

[5] Walter Benjamin, »Das Kunstwerk im Zeitalter seiner technischen Reproduzierbarkeit [Zweite Fassung]« (1935/36), in Gesammelte Schriften, VII (1), Suhrkamp, 1989.

[6] Émile Zola, Mon Salon (1866), in Œuvres complètes, II, Nouveau Monde, 2002.

[7] Richard Shiff, Cézanne and the End of Impressionism: A Study of the Theory, Technique, and Critical Evaluation of Modern Art, The University of Chicago Press, 1984.

[8] Jean Dubuffet, Asphyxiante culture, Jean-Jacques Pauvert, 1968.

[9] Conrad Fiedler, Der Ursprung der Künstlerischen Thätigkeit, BiblioBazaar, 2008.

[10] André Malraux, La Psychologie de l’Art tome 1: Le Musée imaginaire, Gallimard, 1947.

 

著者: (AKIMARU Tomoki)

美術評論家・美学者・美術史家・キュレーター。1997年多摩美術大学美術学部芸術学科卒業、1998年インターメディウム研究所アートセオリー専攻修了、2001年大阪大学大学院文学研究科文化表現論専攻美学文芸学専修修士課程修了、2009年京都芸術大学大学院芸術研究科美術史専攻博士課程単位取得満期退学、2012年京都芸術大学より博士学位(学術)授与。2013年に博士論文『ポール・セザンヌと蒸気鉄道――近代技術による視覚の変容』(晃洋書房)を出版し、2014年に同書で比較文明学会研究奨励賞(伊東俊太郎賞)受賞。2010年4月から2012年3月まで京都大学こころの未来研究センターで連携研究員として連携研究プロジェクト「近代技術的環境における心性の変容の図像解釈学的研究」の研究代表を務める。主なキュレーションに、現代京都藝苑2015「悲とアニマ——モノ学・感覚価値研究会」展(会場:北野天満宮、会期:2015年3月7日〜2015年3月14日)、現代京都藝苑2015「素材と知覚——『もの派』の根源を求めて」展(第1会場:遊狐草舎、第2会場:Impact Hub Kyoto〔虚白院 内〕、会期:2015年3月7日〜2015年3月22日)、現代京都藝苑2021「悲とアニマⅡ~いのちの帰趨~」展(第1会場:両足院〔建仁寺塔頭〕、第2会場:The Terminal KYOTO、会期:2021年11月19日~2021年11月28日)、「藤井湧泉——龍花春早 猫虎懶眠」展(第1会場:高台寺、第2会場:圓徳院、第3会場:掌美術館、会期:2022年3月3日~2022年5月6日)等。2023年に高木慶子・秋丸知貴『グリーフケア・スピリチュアルケアに携わる人達へ』(クリエイツかもがわ・2023年)出版。

2010年4月-2012年3月: 京都大学こころの未来研究センター連携研究員
2011年4月-2013年3月: 京都大学地域研究統合情報センター共同研究員
2011年4月-2016年3月: 京都大学こころの未来研究センター共同研究員
2016年4月-: 滋賀医科大学非常勤講師
2017年4月-2024年3月: 上智大学グリーフケア研究所非常勤講師
2020年4月-2023年3月: 上智大学グリーフケア研究所特別研究員
2021年4月-2024年3月: 京都ノートルダム女子大学非常勤講師
2022年4月-: 京都芸術大学非常勤講師

【投稿予定】

■ 秋丸知貴『近代とは何か?――抽象絵画の思想史的研究』
序論 「象徴形式」の美学
第1章 「自然」概念の変遷
第2章 「象徴形式」としての一点透視遠近法
第3章 「芸術」概念の変遷
第4章 抽象絵画における形式主義と神秘主義
第5章 自然的環境から近代技術的環境へ
第6章 抽象絵画における機械主義
第7章 スーパーフラットとヤオヨロイズム

■ 秋丸知貴『美とアウラ――ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの美学』
第1章 ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの「アウラ」概念について
第2章 ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの「アウラの凋落」概念について
第3章 ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの「感覚的知覚の正常な範囲の外側」の問題について
第4章 ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの芸術美学――「自然との関係における美」と「歴史との関係における美」
第5章 ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの複製美学――「複製技術時代の芸術作品」再考

■ 秋丸知貴『近代絵画と近代技術――ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの「アウラ」概念を手掛りに』
序論 近代技術的環境における心性の変容の図像解釈学的研究
第1章 近代絵画と近代技術
第2章 印象派と大都市群集
第3章 セザンヌと蒸気鉄道
第4章 フォーヴィズムと自動車
第5章 「象徴形式」としてのキュビズム
第6章 近代絵画と飛行機
第7章 近代絵画とガラス建築(1)――印象派を中心に
第8章 近代絵画とガラス建築(2)――キュビズムを中心に
第9章 近代絵画と近代照明(1)――フォーヴィズムを中心に
第10章 近代絵画と近代照明(2)――抽象絵画を中心に
第11章 近代絵画と写真(1)――象徴派を中心に
第12章 近代絵画と写真(2)――エドゥアール・マネ、印象派を中心に
第13章 近代絵画と写真(3)――後印象派、新印象派を中心に
第14章 近代絵画と写真(4)――フォーヴィズム、キュビズムを中心に
第15章 抽象絵画と近代技術――ヴァルター・ベンヤミンの「アウラ」概念を手掛りに

■ 秋丸知貴『ポール・セザンヌと蒸気鉄道 補遺』
第1章 ポール・セザンヌの生涯と作品――19世紀後半のフランス画壇の歩みを背景に
第2章 ポール・セザンヌの中心点(1)――自筆書簡と実作品を手掛かりに
第3章 ポール・セザンヌの中心点(2)――自筆書簡と実作品を手掛かりに
第4章 ポール・セザンヌと写真――近代絵画における写真の影響の一側面

■ Tomoki Akimaru Cézanne and the Railway
Cézanne and the Railway (1): A Transformation of Visual Perception in the 19th Century
Cézanne and the Railway (2): The Earliest Railway Painting Among the French Impressionists
Cézanne and the Railway (3): His Railway Subjects in Aix-en-Provence

■ 秋丸知貴『岸田劉生と東京――近代日本絵画におけるリアリズムの凋落』
序論 日本人と写実表現
第1章 岸田吟香と近代日本洋画――洋画家岸田劉生の誕生
第2章 岸田劉生の写実回帰 ――大正期の細密描写
第3章 岸田劉生の東洋回帰――反西洋的近代化
第4章 日本における近代化の精神構造
第5章 岸田劉生と東京

■ 秋丸知貴『〈もの派〉の根源――現代日本美術における伝統的感受性』
第1章 関根伸夫《位相-大地》論――日本概念派からもの派へ
第2章 現代日本美術における自然観――関根伸夫の《位相-大地》(1968年)から《空相-黒》(1978年)への展開を中心に
第3章 Qui sommes-nous? ――小清水漸の1966年から1970年の芸術活動の考察
第4章 現代日本美術における土着性――小清水漸の《垂線》(1969年)から《表面から表面へ-モニュメンタリティー》(1974年)への展開を中心に
第5章 現代日本彫刻における土着性――小清水漸の《a tetrahedron-鋳鉄》(1974年)から「作業台」シリーズへの展開を中心に

■ 秋丸知貴『藤井湧泉論――知られざる現代京都の超絶水墨画家』
第1章 藤井湧泉(黄稚)――中国と日本の美的昇華
第2章 藤井湧泉と伊藤若冲――京都・相国寺で花開いた中国と日本の美意識(前編)
第3章 藤井湧泉と伊藤若冲――京都・相国寺で花開いた中国と日本の美意識(中編)
第4章 藤井湧泉と伊藤若冲――京都・相国寺で花開いた中国と日本の美意識(後編)
第5章 藤井湧泉と京都の禅宗寺院――一休寺・相国寺・金閣寺・林光院・高台寺・圓徳院
第6章 藤井湧泉の《妖女赤夜行進図》――京都・高台寺で咲き誇る新時代の百鬼夜行図
第7章 藤井湧泉の《雲龍嘯虎襖絵》――兵庫・大蔵院に鳴り響く新時代の龍虎図(前編)
第8章 藤井湧泉の《雲龍嘯虎襖絵》――兵庫・大蔵院に鳴り響く新時代の龍虎図(後編)
第9章 藤井湧泉展――龍花春早・猫虎懶眠
第10章 藤井湧泉展――水墨雲龍・極彩猫虎
第11章 藤井湧泉展――龍虎花卉多吉祥
第12章 藤井湧泉展――ネコトラとアンパラレル・ワールド

■ 秋丸知貴『比較文化と比較芸術』
序論 比較の重要性
第1章 西洋と日本における自然観の比較
第2章 西洋と日本における宗教観の比較
第3章 西洋と日本における人間観の比較
第4章 西洋と日本における動物観の比較
第5章 西洋と日本における絵画観(画題)の比較
第6章 西洋と日本における絵画観(造形)の比較
第7章 西洋と日本における彫刻観の比較
第8章 西洋と日本における建築観の比較
第9章 西洋と日本における庭園観の比較
第10章 西洋と日本における料理観の比較
第11章 西洋と日本における文学観の比較
第12章 西洋と日本における演劇観の比較
第13章 西洋と日本における恋愛観の比較
第14章 西洋と日本における死生観の比較

■ 秋丸知貴『ケアとしての芸術』
第1章 グリーフケアとしての和歌――「辞世」を巡る考察を中心に
第2章 グリーフケアとしての芸道――オイゲン・ヘリゲル『弓と禅』を手掛かりに
第3章 絵画制作におけるケアの基本構造――形式・内容・素材の観点から
第4章 絵画鑑賞におけるケアの基本構造――代弁と共感の観点から
第5章 フィンセント・ファン・ゴッホ論
第6章 エドヴァルト・ムンク論
第7章 草間彌生論
第8章 アウトサイダー・アート論

■ 秋丸知貴『芸術創造の死生学』
第1章 アンリ・エランベルジェの「創造の病い」概念について
第2章 ジークムント・フロイトの「昇華」概念について
第3章 カール・グスタフ・ユングの「個性化」概念について
第4章 エーリッヒ・ノイマンの「中心向性」概念について
第5章 エイブラハム・マズローの「至高体験」概念について
第6章 ミハイ・チクセントミハイの「フロー」概念について

http://tomokiakimaru.web.fc2.com/